Many math books that I’ve read referred me to other books for the proof of the equivalence of the Axiom of Choice and Zorn’s Lemma. This afternoon, I spent more than two hours to understand the proof that the later implies and former in Topology written by Davis.
- Set up a non-empty partially ordered set $(\mathcal{P},\le)$
- Let $\mathcal{T}$ be any non-empty chain in $\mathcal{P}$.
- Prove that $\cup \mathcal{T} \in \mathcal{P}$.
- Apply Zorn’s Lemma to get a maximal element $g \in \mathcal{P}$.
- Use the maximality of $g$ to claim that the domain of $g$ equals the family of non-empty subsets $(S_i)_{i \in I}$ from which elements $(x_i)_{i \in I}$ are chosen.
In the book, $\le$ means function extension, and
Step (3) is proved step-by-step according to the definition of
$\mathcal{P}$. Usually, suppose that $(x_1,y_1),(x_2,y_2) \in f$,
$x_1 = x_2 \implies y_1 = y_2$. The book uses the contrapositive form
of this statement. I was stuck at the sentence Now, for a set to
be an element of $dom\cup\mathcal{T}$, it must be an element of some
member of $\mathcal{T}$
. At first, I omitted the phrase "some
member of", and stopped for half an hour. Reading the next sentence
Hence $dom\cup\mathcal{T} \subseteq (S_i)_{i \in I}$
, I knew
how to interpret the sentence where I was stuck: if $S \in
dom\cup\mathcal{T}$, $\exists f \in \mathcal{T}$ such that $S \in
dom\,f$. Since $f \in \mathcal{T} \subseteq \mathcal{P}$, $dom\,f
\subseteq (S_i)_{i \in I}$. Then $S \in (S_i)_{i \in I}$, and thus
$dom\cup\mathcal{T} \subseteq (S_i)_{i \in I}$.